43 Facts About Ontological argument

1.

An ontological argument is a philosophical argument, made from an ontological basis, that is advanced in support of the existence of God.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,543
2.

Just as the ontological argument has been popular, a number of criticisms and objections have been mounted.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,544
3.

Gaunilo, suggesting that the ontological argument could be used to prove the existence of anything, uses the analogy of a perfect island.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,545
4.

Ontological argument contrasted the ontological argument with the cosmological and physio-theoretical arguments.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,546
5.

Craig argues that an argument can be classified as ontological if it attempts to deduce the existence of God, along with other necessary truths, from his definition.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,547

Related searches

God Descartes Leibniz William
6.

Anselm's Ontological argument was not presented in order to prove God's existence; rather, Proslogion was a work of meditation in which he documented how the idea of God became self-evident to him.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,548
7.

Ontological argument suggests that even "the fool" can understand this concept, and this understanding itself means that the being must exist in the mind.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,549
8.

Ontological argument argued that if something can be conceived not to exist, then something greater can be conceived.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,550
9.

Ontological argument suggested that the concept of God is that of a supremely perfect being, holding all perfections.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,551
10.

Ontological argument seems to have assumed that existence is a predicate of a perfection.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,552
11.

Ontological argument starts off by saying: "whether there is a God, this, we say, can be proved".

FactSnippet No. 1,575,553
12.

Ontological argument proposed that, unless the coherence of a supremely perfect being could be demonstrated, the ontological argument fails.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,554
13.

Ontological argument reasoned that all perfections can exist together in a single entity, and that Descartes' argument is still valid.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,555
14.

Ontological argument rejected the argument on the basis that existence precedes essence, or that the existence of human beings is more fundamental than their essence.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,556
15.

Sadra put forward a new Ontological argument, known as Seddiqin Argument or Argument of the Righteous.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,557
16.

Ontological argument's work is published today as incomplete, with only part of his Cosmological Argument intact.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,558
17.

The Ontological argument was constructed by Godel but not published until long after his death.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,559
18.

Ontological argument provided an argument based on modal logic; he uses the conception of properties, ultimately concluding with God's existence.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,560
19.

Ontological argument warned against interpreting "positive" as being morally or aesthetically "good", as this includes negative characteristics.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,561
20.

Ontological argument suggested that if these positive properties form a set, there is no reason to believe that any such set exists which is theologically interesting, or that there is only one set of positive properties which is theologically interesting.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,562
21.

Jordon Sobel writes that Malcolm is incorrect in assuming that the Ontological argument he is expounding is to be found entirely in Proslogion chapter 3.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,563
22.

Ontological argument argued that, if Malcolm does prove the necessary existence of the greatest possible being, it follows that there is a being which exists in all worlds whose greatness in some worlds is not surpassed.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,564
23.

Ontological argument argued that it is possible for a being with maximal greatness to exist, so a being with maximal greatness exists in a possible world.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,565
24.

Martin proposed parodies of the Ontological argument, suggesting that the existence of anything can be demonstrated with Plantinga's Ontological argument, provided it is defined as perfect or special in every possible world.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,566
25.

Ontological argument stated that one only has the epistemic right to accept the premise if one understands the nested modal operators, and that if one understands them within the system S5—without which the argument fails—then one understands that "possibly necessarily" is in essence the same as "necessarily".

FactSnippet No. 1,575,567

Related searches

God Descartes Leibniz William
26.

Ontological argument started with the 8th–9th-century AD Indian philosopher Sankara's dictum that if something is impossible, we cannot have a perception that it is the case.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,568
27.

One of the earliest recorded objections to Anselm's Ontological argument was raised by one of Anselm's contemporaries, Gaunilo of Marmoutiers.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,569
28.

Ontological argument invited his reader to conceive an island "more excellent" than any other island.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,570
29.

Ontological argument suggested that, according to Anselm's proof, this island must necessarily exist, as an island that exists would be more excellent.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,571
30.

Ontological argument offered a further criticism of Anselm's ontological argument, suggesting that the notion of God cannot be conceived, as Anselm had asserted.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,572
31.

Ontological argument argued that many theists would accept that God, by nature, cannot be fully comprehended.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,573
32.

Ontological argument suggested that only a being with necessary existence can fulfill the remit of "that than which nothing greater can be conceived".

FactSnippet No. 1,575,574
33.

Ontological argument claimed that the no devil corollary is a strong challenge, as it "underwrites" the no devil corollary, which "threatens Anselm's argument at its very foundations".

FactSnippet No. 1,575,575
34.

Ontological argument suggested that people cannot know the nature of God and, therefore, cannot conceive of God in the way Anselm proposed.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,576
35.

The ontological argument would be meaningful only to someone who understands the essence of God completely.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,577
36.

Ontological argument believed that existence is not a quality, so a completely perfect being need not exist.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,578
37.

Ontological argument's criticism is primarily directed at Descartes, but attacks Leibniz.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,579
38.

Ontological argument considers examples of necessary propositions, such as "a triangle has three angles", and rejects the transfer of this logic to the existence of God.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,580
39.

Ontological argument proposes that existence is not a predicate, or quality.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,581
40.

Ontological argument asserts that God exists outside the realm of experience and nature.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,582
41.

Ontological argument continued by arguing that there is no reason to view the creation of the world as "the most marvellous achievement imaginable".

FactSnippet No. 1,575,583
42.

American philosopher of religion William L Rowe notably believed that the structure of the ontological argument was such that it inherently begs the question of God's existence, that is to say, that one must have a presupposed belief in God's existence in order to accept the argument's conclusion.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,584
43.

The ontological argument assumes the definition of God purported by classical theism: that God is omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect.

FactSnippet No. 1,575,585