128 Facts About Kant

1.

Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,984
2.

Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of the senses as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition, so that we have a priori cognition of those objects.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,985
3.

Kant believed that reason is the source of morality, and that aesthetics arise from a faculty of disinterested judgment.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,986
4.

Kant's views continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy, especially the fields of epistemology, ethics, political theory, and post-modern aesthetics.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,987
5.

Kant attempted to explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond what he believed to be the failures of traditional philosophy and metaphysics.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,988
6.

Kant wanted to put an end to what he saw as an era of futile and speculative theories of human experience, while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as Hume.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,989
7.

Kant regarded himself as showing the way past the impasse between rationalists and empiricists, and is widely held to have synthesized both traditions in his thought.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,990
8.

Kant was an exponent of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation, and that perhaps this could be the culminating stage of world history.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,991
9.

Beyond his religious views, Kant has been criticized for the racism presented in some of his lesser-known papers, such as "On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy" and "On the Different Races of Man".

FactSnippet No. 1,201,992
10.

Kant published other important works on ethics, religion, law, aesthetics, astronomy, and history during his lifetime.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,993
11.

Kant's mother, Anna Regina Reuter, was born in Konigsberg to a father from Nuremberg.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,994
12.

Kant's father, Johann Georg Kant, was a German harness maker from Memel, at the time Prussia's most northeastern city .

FactSnippet No. 1,201,995
13.

Kant believed that his paternal grandfather Hans Kant was of Scottish origin.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,996
14.

Kant was brought up in a Pietist household that stressed religious devotion, humility, and a literal interpretation of the Bible.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,997
15.

Kant's education was strict, punitive and disciplinary, and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,998
16.

Kant apparently lived a very strict and disciplined life; it was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks.

FactSnippet No. 1,201,999
17.

Kant never married, but seems to have had a rewarding social life—he was a popular teacher, as well as a modestly successful author even before starting on his major philosophical works.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,000
18.

Kant had a circle of friends with whom he frequently met—among them Joseph Green, an English merchant in Konigsberg, whom reportedly he first spoke to in an argument in 1763 or before.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,001
19.

Kant joined the conversation, which soon turned to unusual current events in the world.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,002
20.

Kant took the side of the Americans, and this upset Green, and he challenged Kant to a fight.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,003
21.

Kant typically referred to indigenous peoples of America as "Americans", as well.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,004
22.

Kant first attended the Collegium Fridericianum from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,005
23.

Kant studied the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz and Christian Wolff under Martin Knutzen, a rationalist who was familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of Isaac Newton.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,006
24.

Kant dissuaded Kant from idealism, the idea that reality is purely mental, which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded in a negative light.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,007
25.

The theory of transcendental idealism that Kant later included in the Critique of Pure Reason was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,008
26.

Kant became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Konigsberg, but continued his scholarly research.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,009
27.

Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics, but he made significant contributions to other disciplines.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,010
28.

In 1755, Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Konigsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics, physics, logic and metaphysics.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,011
29.

In 1756 Kant published three papers on the 1755 Lisbon earthquake.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,012
30.

In 1757, Kant began lecturing on geography making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,013
31.

Kant correctly deduced that the Milky Way was a large disk of stars, which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,014
32.

Kant further suggested that other distant "nebulae" might be other galaxies.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,015
33.

In 1766 Kant wrote Dreams of a Spirit-Seer which dealt with the writings of Emanuel Swedenborg.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,016
34.

In defense of this appointment, Kant wrote his inaugural dissertation De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,017
35.

Issue that vexed Kant was central to what 20th-century scholars called "the philosophy of mind".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,018
36.

Kant saw that the mind could not function as an empty container that simply receives data from outside.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,019
37.

Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these "pre-critical" writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,020
38.

At age 46, Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher, and much was expected of him.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,021
39.

In correspondence with his ex-student and friend Markus Herz, Kant admitted that, in the inaugural dissertation, he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,022
40.

Kant needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge—i.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,023
41.

Kant credited David Hume with awakening him from a "dogmatic slumber" in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and natural philosophy.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,024
42.

Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism, and he set himself to solving these problems.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,025
43.

When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781, the result was the Critique of Pure Reason.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,026
44.

Kant countered Hume's empiricism by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind, independent of experience.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,027
45.

Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited a priori, and that intuition is consequently distinct from objective reality.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,028
46.

Kant published a second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787, heavily revising the first parts of the book.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,029
47.

Kant continued to develop his moral philosophy, notably in 1788's Critique of Practical Reason and 1797's Metaphysics of Morals.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,030
48.

Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book, routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,031
49.

Kant then published his response to the King's reprimand and explained himself, in the preface of The Conflict of the Faculties.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,032
50.

Kant wrote a number of semi-popular essays on history, religion, politics and other topics.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,033
51.

Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,034
52.

In 1800, a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jasche published a manual of logic for teachers called Logik, which he had prepared at Kant's request.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,035
53.

Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest, rigorously scheduled habits, which have been referred to as clocklike.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,036
54.

Originally, Kant was buried inside the cathedral, but in 1880 his remains were moved to a neo-Gothic chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,037
55.

The incident was apparently connected with a recent vote to rename Khrabrovo Airport, where Kant was in the lead for a while, prompting Russian nationalist resentment.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,038
56.

Kant maintained that one ought to think autonomously, free of the dictates of external authority.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,039
57.

Kant's work reconciled many of the differences between the rationalist and empiricist traditions of the 18th century.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,040
58.

Kant had a decisive impact on the Romantic and German Idealist philosophies of the 19th century.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,041
59.

Kant's work has been a starting point for many 20th century philosophers.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,042
60.

Kant asserted that, because of the limitations of argumentation in the absence of irrefutable evidence, no one could really know whether there is a God and an afterlife or not.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,043
61.

Kant drew a parallel between the Copernican revolution and the epistemology of his new transcendental philosophy, involving two interconnected foundations of his "critical philosophy":.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,044
62.

Kant argued that the rational order of the world as known by science was not just the accidental accumulation of sense perceptions.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,045
63.

However, Kant speaks of the thing in itself or transcendental object as a product of the understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,046
64.

The specifics of Kant's account generated immediate and lasting controversy.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,047
65.

Kant defines his theory of perception in his very influential 1781 work the Critique of Pure Reason, which has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and epistemology in modern philosophy.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,048
66.

Kant maintains that understanding of the external world had its foundations not merely in experience, but in both experience and a priori concepts, thus offering a non-empiricist critique of rationalist philosophy, which is what has been referred to as his Copernican revolution.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,049
67.

Kant asserts that experience is based on the perception of external objects and a priori knowledge.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,050
68.

Against metaphysical time and space Kant explains they are not things in themselves but mere shape of the way we feel things.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,051
69.

Kant adds that space itself depends on time, because nothing can be in space without being within time.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,052
70.

Kant deemed it obvious that we have some objective knowledge of the world, such as, say, Newtonian physics.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,053
71.

The parallelism with Kant's categories is obvious: quantity, quality, relation and modality .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,054
72.

Kant ran into a problem with his theory that the mind plays a part in producing objective knowledge.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,055
73.

Kant developed his ethics, or moral philosophy, in three works: Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, Critique of Practical Reason, and Metaphysics of Morals .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,056
74.

In Groundwork, Kant tries to convert our everyday, obvious, rational knowledge of morality into philosophical knowledge.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,057
75.

Kant is known for his theory that there is a single moral obligation, which he called the "Categorical Imperative", and is derived from the concept of duty.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,058
76.

Kant defines the demands of moral law as "categorical imperatives".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,059
77.

Kant stated that the moral means and ends can be applied to the categorical imperative, that rational beings can pursue certain "ends" using the appropriate "means".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,060
78.

Kant believed that the moral law is a principle of reason itself, and is not based on contingent facts about the world, such as what would make us happy, but to act on the moral law which has no other motive than "worthiness to be happy".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,061
79.

Unlike a hypothetical imperative, a categorical imperative is an unconditional obligation; it has the force of an obligation regardless of our will or desires In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant enumerated three formulations of the categorical imperative that he believed to be roughly equivalent.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,062
80.

Kant believed that, if an action is not done with the motive of duty, then it is without moral value.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,063
81.

Kant thought that every action should have pure intention behind it; otherwise, it is meaningless.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,064
82.

In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, Kant posited the "counter-utilitarian idea that there is a difference between preferences and values, and that considerations of individual rights temper calculations of aggregate utility", a concept that is an axiom in economics:.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,065
83.

Phrase quoted by Kant, which is used to summarize the counter-utilitarian nature of his moral philosophy, is Fiat justitia, pereat mundus, which he translates loosely as "Let justice reign even if all the rascals in the world should perish from it".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,066
84.

An agent's maxim, according to Kant, is his "subjective principle of human actions": that is, what the agent believes is his reason to act.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,067
85.

Commentators, starting in the 20th century, have tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion, though this was not the prevalent view in the 19th century.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,068
86.

Kant articulates his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations to those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,069
87.

Kant sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one's maxims.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,070
88.

Nevertheless, other interpreters consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,071
89.

Kant sees in Jesus Christ the affirmation of a "pure moral disposition of the heart" that "can make man well-pleasing to God".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,072
90.

However, many interpreters, including Allen W Wood and Lawrence Pasternack, now agree with Stephen Palmquist's claim that a better way of reading Kant's Religion is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,073
91.

Kant calls practical "everything that is possible through freedom", and the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions but are held analogously with the universal law of causality are moral laws.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,074
92.

Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,075
93.

Baumgarten, who wrote Aesthetica, Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system, utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,076
94.

Kant believed that a judgement of taste shares characteristics engaged in a moral judgement: both are disinterested, and we hold them to be universal.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,077
95.

Kant developed a theory of humor that has been interpreted as an "incongruity" theory.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,078
96.

Kant illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the Critique of Judgment.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,079
97.

Kant thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,080
98.

Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a "refined" value in his Idea of A Universal History .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,081
99.

In Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,082
100.

Kant believed that universal history leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace, but his theory was not pragmatic.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,083
101.

Kant's political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,084
102.

Kant opposed "democracy, " which at his time meant direct democracy, believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,085
103.

Kant lectured on anthropology, the study of human nature, for twenty-three and a half years.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,086
104.

Introduction to Kant's Anthropology was translated into English and published by the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy series in 2006.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,087
105.

Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study, long before the field gained popularity, and his texts are considered to have advanced the field.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,088
106.

Kant was the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,089
107.

Kant analyzed the nature of the Hippocrates-Galen four temperaments and plotted them in two dimensions: "activation", or energetic aspect of behaviour, and "orientation on emotionality".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,090
108.

Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend racism, and some have claimed that he was one of the central figures in the birth of modern scientific racism.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,091
109.

Kant goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a "great hindustani man" is one who has "gone far in the art of deception and has much money".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,092
110.

Kant stated that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,093
111.

About black Africans, Kant wrote that "they can be educated but only as servants, that is they allow themselves to be trained".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,094
112.

Kant calls them unmotivated, lacking affect, passion and love, describing them as too weak for labor, unfit for any culture, and too phlegmatic for diligence.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,095
113.

Kant said the Native Americans are "far below the Negro, who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,096
114.

Kant stated that "instead of assimilation, which was intended by the melting together of the various races, Nature has here made a law of just the opposite".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,097
115.

Kant believed that in the future all races would be extinguished, except that of the whites.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,098
116.

Charles W Mills wrote that Kant has been "sanitized for public consumption", his racist works conveniently ignored.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,099
117.

Pauline Kleingeld argues that while Kant was indeed a staunch advocate of scientific racism for much of his career, his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,100
118.

In particular, she argues that Kant unambiguously rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non-whites in Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,101
119.

Kant's ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,102
120.

Influential English Romantic poet and aesthetic philosopher Samuel Taylor Coleridge was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him, and of German idealism generally, in the UK and the USA.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,103
121.

Kant's thinking on religion was used in Britain to challenge the decline in religious faith in the nineteenth century.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,104
122.

Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new positivism at that time.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,105
123.

Kant's motto was "Back to Kant", and a re-examination of his ideas began .

FactSnippet No. 1,202,106
124.

Kant went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a "critical history of modernity, rooted in Kant".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,107
125.

Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of synthetic a priori knowledge, which means they are necessary and universal, yet known through intuition.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,108
126.

Mou Zongsan's study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou's personal philosophy, namely New Confucianism.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,109
127.

Kant's influence has extended to the social, behavioral, and physical sciences, as in the sociology of Max Weber, the psychology of Jean Piaget and Carl Gustav Jung, and the linguistics of Noam Chomsky.

FactSnippet No. 1,202,110
128.

Kant held the view that "[I]f one does not want to assert that relativity theory goes against reason, one cannot retain the a priori concepts and norms of Kant's system".

FactSnippet No. 1,202,111